Research and Practice: Universities and Schools
Gene V Glass
Nelle Moore
Division of Educational Leadership & Policy Studies
College of Education
Arizona State University
(Paper presented to the Arizona Educational Research
Organization at its Second Annual Meeting, 20 October 1989,and heavily edited
afterwards.)
Thesis: The
Universities, through their efforts in research and scholarship, do not
contribute materially to the practice of education. The soft social sciences
(social psychology, behavioral psychology, clinical psychology, sociology and
the like) are incapable of significantly advancing the practice of the minor
professions (teaching, social work, counseling, and nursing, to name a few).
The schools' hope that the universities will advance knowledge and make
discoveries that will solve education's problems is a vain hope.
One of us believed what
will be said here today in 1972 when he read the following remarks made by the
philosopher of science Thomas Kuhn: "I'm not sure that there can now be
such a thing as really productive educational research. It is not clear that
one yet has the conceptual research categories, research tools, and properly
selected problems that will lead to increased
understanding of the educational process. There is a general assumption that if
you've got a big problem, the way to solve it is by the application of science.
All you have to do is call on the right people and put enough money in and in a
matter of a few years, you will have it. But it doesn't work that way, and it
never will." (Quoted in Dershimer, 1970, p.79.)
This belief was given an intellectual foundation by Paul Meehl's
classic "Two Knights" paper in 1978, in which he enumerated twenty
reasons why fields like educational research do not make progress. After thirty
years in the academic world, one of us now believes this thesis even more
confidently, because he has seen how the culture of the research university
molds its faculty into researchers who have little hope of improving the
practice of education.
The wide gulf between
research and practice arises from two sources, basically: the near
impossibility of productive elucidatory inquiry on the practice of schooling
and the culture of universities in which the minor professions have had to
subjugate themselves (intellectually and professionally) to the social and
behavioral sciences. Let's examine each source in turn.
Why Soft Science
Doesn't Progress.
Two scholars stand like lamp-posts illuminating the path we walk. Paul Meehl and Lee Cronbach's contributions
to our thinking about the problems of research in the soft sciences go back
over thirty years to their collaboration on the construct validity of tests.
Though they never collaborated again to our knowledge, in recent years their
assessment of the scientific enterprise in the soft social sciences, and in
education, have converged on a sort of doom—or perhaps
"modesty" is a better word—that the
profession largely wishes to ignore.
Lee Cronbach
spoke on "Prudent Aspirations for Social Inquiry" on the occasion of
the 50th anniversary of the dedication of the Social Science Research Building
at the University of Chicago in December of 1979: "The profession is proud
of much work old and new and of the influence social inquiry has had, yet is troubled
that little theory cumulates and distressed that many recommended practical
actions fail. The persons most disappointed are the ones in the profession and
in the world of action who hoped that our conclusions
would directly indicate what social policy should be. Findings of social
science can rarely or never identify 'right' courses of action. Fortunately,
today's profession is coming to see the rationalist, scientistic
ideal as no more than an infantile dream of omnipotence. The present mood, one
hopes, bespeaks an institution on the brink of adulthood, ready to claim a role
within its capabilities and aware that waiting for its Newton is as pointless
as waiting for Godot." (p.61)
Elucidatory inquiry
("science") on education runs aground of a host of difficulties that
have daunted attempts to control and predict human enterprises. The record of
success in these areas (the sciences of the artificial, to use Herbert Simon's
phrase) has not been good. Our attempts to build a scientific basis for
technical advancement of education encounter the following problems, according
to Meehl: the difficulty of slicing and naming the
raw behavioral flux, problems of naming situations, open constructs, individual
differences in response, the absence of meaningful units of measure, divergent
causality, unknown critical events, nuisance variables, feedback loops,
autocatalytic processes, essentially random influences, the sheer number of
variables affecting behavior, culture, intentionality, and the uniqueness of
context. There is scant cause for optimism about the scientific enterprise in
education. Related fields (nursing, social work, counseling, law enforcement)
have no great successes to point to for encouragement. The idea that
universities will discover knowledge that practitioners will apply dies hard,
but its demise is certain.
There is a sense in
which research, scholarship, and science shape practice in education, but only
very remotely and over decades; this happens through the creation and
promulgation of metaphors and images that are taken up as popular knowledge and
then guide action. But we do not speak of this interpretation here since it is
not the sense of research into practice that practitioners expect. They expect
to read directions in the form of propositions on what to do to make things
better. (Glass, Cronbach, Lakoff
& Johnson).
What Universities Do
to Education Faculty
Professional school faculty in the modern American university are pressured to
adopt a style of research that stands little chance of contributing to improved
practice. The
pressure is exerted primarily at the
points where faculty stand for tenure and promotion to "full"; and it
is applied by faculty in the social and behavioral sciences. One of us has sat
on faculty promotion and tenure committees in three different universities for
a quarter century. The experience has been absolutely the same in every place
and at all times. Sooner or later, before an aspirant for tenure is granted the
prize, that person's "papers" (it is assumed that
what a person contributes can be captured in print) must pass a committee of
faculty drawn from throughout the university.
Engineers are sometimes loathe to judge artists, and historians occasionally demur
when the candidate's accomplishments disappear into some uncharted recess of
the atom. But the social sciences speak with authority when the case before the
committee comes from one of the minor professions—indeed, some
psychologists, economists and what-have-you virtually regard professions as
little more than arenas for the application of social science knowledge. The
record of publishing that one must present to win this group's approval is one
of several short (six to ten printed pages), empirical reports of experiments
or surveys; if the topic of the works changes too frequently the work is said
to be "not programmatic," a stinging indictment for which the
candidate may not be able to advance an adequate defense.
This entire sub-culture
of brief, written research reports in archival journals reveals the concept of inquiry which its guardians hold. Knowledge is established
through a series of well-controlled empirical forays and is packaged in the
form of verbal propositions which are general and last forever: "Do A when
confronted with circumstances X and desirous of achieving state Alpha; do B
under circumstances Y." Much has been written in our professional house
organs in recent years about the historical origins of this particular view of
the world and inquiry into it. Suffice it to say that this simplified
perspective on knowledge discovery and use is under withering attack everywhere
and loses defenders almost daily. Kenneth Prewitt, in testimony to the House
Subcommittee on Science, Research and Technology (Items, Vol. 34, No. 1, March
1980, pp.1-4), spoke of the diminished aspirations of the contemporary social
sciences: "The complexity of the problems for which the social and
behavioral sciences might be helpful are always going to be one step ahead of
the problem-solving abilities of those sciences.... They are sciences whose
progress is marked, and whose usefulness is measured, less by the achievement
of consensus or the solving of problems than by a refinement of debate and a
sharpening of the intelligence upon which collective management of human
affairs depends." (p. 3)
The reasons why
professional school faculty are subjected to this influence stem from the
history of the development of the professions and the universities in this
country. Researchers and scholars in Europe, for example, do not suffer as
greatly the unhelpful influence of the norms that prevail in American
universities. We shall spend a little time recapping this history.
The pressures which
education faculty feel as members of both a profession and an academic
community have their roots in the circumstances surrounding the rise of the
large state universities in the United States around the turn of the 20th
century. It is important that we understand these circumstances and how they
predisposed professional schools to be what they are, otherwise
we--university-affiliated researchers on the one hand and practicing educators
on the other--will continue to attribute stupidity and malevolence to each
other as the causes of our inability to talk to and help each other. We cannot
do better in sketching this historical account than to quote Donald Schön at length and verbatim from his book The Reflective
Practitioner (1983); indeed we shall quote him at such length as to be
unseemly were it not that we are receiving no pay to give this talk and Schön might sell a couple of books if you are
convinced by these words that he has written something worth reading further:
"Universities came
of age in the United States, assumed their now familiar structure and styles of
operation, in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries when science
and technology were on the rise and the intellectual hegemony of Positivism was
beginning to be established. Although other traditions of thought were never
wholly extinguished in American universities—indeed, in some places
managed to preserve a kind of local dominance—nevertheless, in the United
States more than in any other nation except Germany, the very heart of the
university was given over to the scientific enterprise, to the ethos of the
Technological Program, and to Positivism.
"Indeed, it was
from the Germanic tradition, carried to the United States after the Civil War
by young American graduates of the German universities, that the new concept of
the university as a multidisciplinary research institution took root in the
United States, first in Johns Hopkins University, the founding of which was
'perhaps the most decisive single event in the history of learning in the
Western hemisphere.' ... " (p. 34)
"With the coming of
the new model of the university, the Positivist epistemology found expression
in normative ideas about the proper division of labor between the university
and the professions. As Thorsten Veblen argued in The Higher Learning in
America, 'The difference between the modern university
and the lower and professional schools is broad and simple; not so much a
difference of degree as of kind.' Theuniversitieshaveahighermissionto'fitmenforalifeofscienceand
scholarship; and [they are] accordingly concerned with such discipline only as
they will give efficiency in the pursuit of knowledge'; whereas the lower
schools are occupied with 'instilling such knowledge and habits as will make
their pupils fit citizens of the world in whatever position in the fabric of
workday life they may fall.' The proper relation between the higher and lower
schools is one of separation and exchange. Quite simply, the professions are to
give their practical problems to the university, and the university, the unique
source of research, is to give back to the professions the new scientific knowledge which it will be their business to apply and test.
Under no conditions are the technical men of the lower schools to be allowed
into the university, for this would put them in a false position
which unavoidably leads them to court
a specious appearance of scholarship and so to invest their technological
discipline with a degree of pedantry and sophistication; whereby it is hoped to
give these schools and their work some scientific and scholarly prestige.
"Veblen's battle
was, of course, quixotic. The evils against which he railed at the University
of Chicago in 1916 were harbingers of a general trend. The survival-oriented
interests of the professions reinforced the interest of university boards of
governors in appropriating schools of useful knowledge. The professions did
enter the new universities, in increasing numbers, until by 1963 Bernard Barber
could write in Daedalus that 'nearly all the well-established professions are
located in the universities.'
"But for this, the
professionalizing occupations paid a price. They had to accept the Positivist
epistemology of practice which was now built into the
very tissue of the universities. And they had also to accept the fundamental
division of labor on which Veblen had placed so great an emphasis. It was to be
the business of university-based scientists and scholars to create the
fundamental theory which professionals and technicians
would apply to practice. ...
"But this division
of labor reflected a hierarchy of kinds of knowledge which was also a ladder of
status. Those who create new theory were thought to be higher in status than
those who apply it, and the schools of 'higher learning' were thought to be
superior to the 'lower.' (pp. 34-37)
Permit us to paraphrase Schön briefly and somewhat more bluntly: American
universities took shape at the same time the professions were being born. It
was in the financial and general survival interests of the professions to align
with this powerful new institution, but the price for "buying in" was
subservience to the traditional bosses of the institution, namely, the basic
disciplines. This subservience, seen in the attempt of the professions to
better themselves by means of adopting the style of
inquiry popular in the basic disciplines, has stunted the evolution of the
professions. The values and the style of the sciences have
been taken on by the professions as their world view. It is hardly safe
in the Academy to question this arrangement.
Myriad anecdotes of not
just the discontinuity between academic research and practice but its actual
conflict could be advanced in illustration of the distance between these two
worlds: the world of theory and the world of practice. But consider just one.
The many members of Maya Ying Lan's architecture
class at Yale submitted designs for the Vietnam War Memorial to the professor,
who incidentally had himself submitted a design to the
national competition along with 14,000 other contestants. The professor was
brutal in his evaluation: "Washington is full of white memorials rising.
This is a dark memorial receding." The grade? B. The professor's design
was not accepted; and, yes, Maya Ying Lan's was.
It would be false to
argue that the universities have not benefited many practical endeavors in the 100 year history of the land grant system in this country.
The counter- examples are virtually legion. Indeed, it is the distinctive
difference between modern American and European universities that the former
were designed to advance the quality of life of the nation. Our point is,
instead, that the modern faculty member in an education college in an ambitious
university is discouraged by the reward structure from any genuine
contributions to the practice of schooling. It is not that we do not hear
sermons calling us to the field; it is that young faculty risk their tenure and
promotion and old faculty risk prestige if they respond. The modern academic
scholar is not averse to giving practical affairs a nudge toward perfection; to
be sure many of them have private fantasies of doing just that,
and successful grant-getting depends
on facility in invoking the possibility of practical gain for one's researches.
But if practice is to benefit from these scholarly endeavors, it will have to
read about them in brief, written accounts published in archival
refereed journals. (One of us no longer reads academic
journals—the same one who has, in the past 25 years, edited three of
them; and that same one has acquired a sense from his colleagues recently that
they don't read them either. They appear to those who have watched them for
some time to be arenas in which young people struggle for tenure or where old
people pontificate.)
Is There Anything
That Can Be Done?
If not science-building, then what can the universities do for the
schools? What "research" will help practice? We're uncertain, but we
have three things currently in mind that are just enough different from the way
we in universities have traditionally conducted our business that they might be
promising: action research (yes, shades of the 1950's, action research is
making a come-back); Donald Schön's ideas about
reflection-in-practice; and the qualitative or naturalistic movement in
educational research.
"Action
research" has a curious ring to it. Many of you in the profession today
are too young to remember when something called "action research"
came around the first time. In the 1950's and early '60's a movement to locate
educational research in the schools with contributions and some participation
by teachers arose out of Teachers College, Columbia, with roots in the work of
Kurt Lewin (or so I have been told). One of my
earliest recollections from graduate school is of a student asking a professor
about action research and seeing the professor curl his lip and spit invective
at the scurrilous misadventure. Today, the movement returns to the U.S. riding
on the shoulders of British Socialism. British scholars and researchers are
seeking to vest the power for educational research in teachers, not in
professional outsiders who would make teachers mere objects of study.
[References] There is much to heed in this development. It is remarkable how
few teacher concerns are taken up by educational researchers,
who often gain the where-with-all to undertake investigations not from teachers
but from teachers' adversaries. There is another commendable feature of
the new Action Research movement, namely, its .... that research of our kind is highly politicized. There are
no politically neutral research questions (except trivial ones), there are not even neutral methods for investigating
research questions. There is always a question of who owns a research agenda.
Not remarkably, perhaps, research often supports or exonerates those
individuals and organizations who have the power to
set the research agenda. Where, for example, is the research on the benefits of
allowing teachers greater autonomy in choosing curriculum, organizing their
workday, supervising and monitoring each other? Why is there
volumes written on principals evaluating teachers and little written on
teachers evaluating principals. To be the object of study in this society is to
be placed in some jeopardy. Those who decide who studies and who gets studied
command a significant measure of political power. The new Action Researchers
remind us of all this. Now if the movement's epistemology can become as
enlightened as its politics, it may stand a chance of catching on and changing
our notion of teachers as researchers rather than as objects of research. There
is a huge difference between being the arrow and being the bull's eye.
Donald Schön's reflection-in-practice is an epistemology of
practice which takes into account the tacit knowledge and artistry inherent in
professional practice. The need for reflection-in-practice
arises when practitioners face situations of uncertainty, instability,
uniqueness, or value conflict. Under these divergent situations,
technical rules and procedures based on general principles and standardized
knowledge are not applicable. To cope with these conditions in practice,
professionals sometimes engage in spontaneous intuitive action and on-the-spot
experiments which lead to new "theories-in-use". However, because
these impromptu experiments usually lack scientific rigor, the knowledge
generated in practice is not accepted as legitimate knowledge. Practitioners intuitive and artistic judgments and actions
are often impossible to justify in words. This feature of reflection-in-
practice only further convinces those who are rooted in Positivism of the
unscientific nature and therefore the unimportance of the knowledge of
practice. The model of technical rationality depends on stable, routine
conditions and fails to account for the ways in which practitioners are able to
cope with divergent situations.
Reflection-in-action is
the process which is central to the art of practice
under divergent conditions. By reflecting on action, even in the midst of it,
the practitioner tries to make hidden assumptions explicit, to examine them
critically in the context of the situation, to make sense of the problems encountered,
to restructure and develop new theories, and to test these new theories in
further action. The reflective practitioner must be willing to experience
confusion, to question prior beliefs, and to invent new strategies on the spot.
By testing these new strategies, the practitioner gains both new understanding
of the situation and at the same time affects the situation. In
reflection-in-practice, there is no problem with implementing the results of
research because the implementation is a part of the research; the exchange
between research and practice is immediate. When a professional reflects in
action (s)he becomes a researcher in the practice
setting.
Reflective research can
also take place outside the immediate context of practice. This kind of research
requires a partnership between researcher and practitioner. The researcher
cannot maintain a distance from practice but instead depends on the
practitioner to supply the material which needs to be
researched. Rather than doing research at the expense of the practitioner in an
adversarial context, reflective research is designed to support the efforts of
the reflective practitioner. Research which focuses on enhancing the
practitioner's ability to reflect-in-action can be of four types, frame analysis,
repertoire- building research, research on fundamental methods of inquiry and
overarching theories, and research on the process of reflection-in-action.
Frame analysis is the study of the ways in which practitioners frame a problem.
Problems usually do not come in neat, labeled packages but are usually first
experienced as "messes". Frame analysis studies the process of
problem identification, conceptualization, and definition. Repertoire-building
research helps to identify and accumulate a portfolio of cases as examples of
the evolution of a problem from framing of the situation to its eventual
resolution. Research on fundamental methods of inquiry is different from the
perspective found in technical rationality. In Schön's
sense, these are the methods and theories of practice which
are used as guidelines for making sense of new situations. This is a form of
"action science" which aims to develop themes or metaphors to help
practitioners understand situations of uniqueness, uncertainty, and
instability. Research on the process of reflection-in-action is an effort to
understand the conditions that encourage or inhibit the development of
reflection-in-action as a style of learning.
Research in education
suffers the same ills as the other minor professions. The context of
educational practice is full of instability, uncertainty, uniqueness, and value
conflicts. Therefore, educational research will not be able to develop a firm
base of scientific knowledge. For this reason, reflective research in support
of reflection-in-practice is a hopeful approach if we want to improve
educational practice. "The dilemma of rigor or relevance may be dissolved
if we can develop an epistemology of practice which places technical problem
solving within a broader context of reflective inquiry." (Schön,1979).
The qualitative movement
in educational research is nothing short of revolutionary. We needn't cast our
minds even as far back as graduate school to recall the time when qualitative
methods (call them naturalistic, ethnographic, anthropological or whatever)
were excluded from our journals, our seminars and our dissertations. In the
span of ten years all that has changed. The graduate program without
qualitative training in it today is viewed as seriously behind the times. There
are many grounds on which the naturalistic approach to research on schools
stands a better chance of affecting practice than the traditional preordinate, quantitative, hypothesis-testing model of
times gone by. For one, it rejects the idea that a complex social system can
best be understood when conceptualized in terms of what behavioral and social
sciences call "variables." One of the clearest illustrations of how
deeply ingrained is the social science mentality is the tendency to confront
practical situations, problems, episodes or phenomena and to see only "variables."
And the very existence of "variables" prompts a host of attendant
concerns: their reliability, their factorial purity, their construct validity,
whether they are endogenous or exogenous, dependent or independent. This
tendency was once an unnatural and foreign style of thinking that had to be
trained into us; we have largely forgotten that we once had to learn it and now
consider it natural and common sense. Yet it is far from clear that the
conceptualization of the world in terms of variables is even productive, let
alone the most productive way of thinking about and coping with the world.
Historians, for one, do not use variables to explain things, and for
significant events and trends they do a better job of predicting than social
scientists. Qualitative researchers, to name another, are apt to view
situations as settings, or scenes or episodes rather than as models of
variables causing and being caused by one another. It is an article of faith
that the qualitative approach will lead to a greater understanding of our
business--educating children--and an increased ability to move the enterprise
in more favorable directions, but it is a faith born of the experience of
reading naturalistic accounts of classrooms and school offices and seeing in
them a verisimilitude lacking in the sterile accounts of experiments and
surveys that emanate from the social science tradition.
One more story
illustrates the problems we in universities are having in attempting to think
about the world of practice and our relationship to it, and at the same time
the story touches on the matter of the qualitative methods and the role they
will be allowed to play in the Academy. Word circulated recently that the
School of Education at the University of Michigan had resolved a long arduous
battle over the distinction between the EdD and the
PhD by deciding that dissertations for the EdD would
be qualitative and those for the PhD would be quantitative. The story, whether
it remains the policy or not, says much about our inability to think clearly
about the practice of education and reconcile it with the pressures we feel in
the universities.
No comments:
Post a Comment